The will to live. Unamuno, Life 7.15

Unamuno believes that it is a mistake to think we can escape from religion, in the broadest sense, because the essential element of religion is something vital in our psyche, a will to live beyond the moment we currently inhabit. Rejecting the historical tradition of any particular religion, and its philosophies, does not liberate us from the need to do the work these tools existed for. So we reinvent that which past ages already invented, in a new form that we can use. Rejecting medieval religions, and their philosophies, doesn't set modern philosophy free from humanity, so in due time a Bergson will arise to cast modern molds for the ancient will to live that persists in us. There is no avoiding the expression of our vitality as some kind of worship that manifests in our language as belief. The role of belief is not limited or limitable to expressing merely the facts; we put facts into myths, which always show us the world in human shapes, shapes that we relate to instinctively, in ways that can never be perfectly or universally rationalized. 


Y el concepto de Dios, siempre redivivo, pues brota del eterno sentimiento de Dios en el hombre, ¿qué es sino la eterna protesta de la vida contra la razón, el nunca vencido instinto de personalización? ¿Y qué es la noción misma de sustancia, sino objetivación de lo más subjetivo, que es la voluntad o la conciencia? Porque la conciencia, aun antes de conocerse como razón, se siente, se toca, se es más bien como voluntad, y como voluntad de no morir. De aquí ese ritmo de que hablábamos en la historia del pensamiento. El positivismo nos trajo una época de racionalismo, es decir, de materialismo, mecanicismo o mortalismo; y he aquí que el vitalismo, el espiritualismo vuelve. ¿Qué han sido los esfuerzos del pragmatismo sino esfuerzos por restaurar la fe en la finalidad humana del universo? ¿Qué son los esfuerzos de un Bergson, v. gr., sobre todo en su obra sobre la evolución creadora, sino forcejeos por restaurar al Dios personal y la conciencia eterna? Y es que la vida no se rinde.

Y de nada sirve querer suprimir ese proceso mitopeico o antropomórfico y racionalizar nuestro pensamiento, como si se pensara sólo para pensar y conocer, y no para vivir. La lengua misma, con la que pensamos, nos lo impide. La lengua, sustancia del pensamiento, es un sistema de metáforas a base mítica y antropomórfica. Y para hacer una filosofía puramente racional, habría que hacerla por fórmulas algebraicas o crear una lengua —una lengua inhumana, es decir, inapta para las necesidades de la vida—para ella, como lo intentó el Dr. Ricardo Avenarius, profesor de filosofía, en Zürich, en su Crítica de la experiencia pura (Kritik der reinen Erfahrung), para evitar los preconceptos. Y este vigoroso esfuerzo de Avenarius, el caudillo de los empiriocriticistas, termina en rigor en puro escepticismo. Él mismo nos lo dice al final del prólogo de la susomentada obra: «Ha tiempo que desapareció la infantil confianza de que nos sea dado hallar la verdad; mientras avanzamos, nos damos cuenta de sus dificultades, y con ello del límite de nuestras fuerzas. ¿Y el fin?... ¡Con tal de que lleguemos a ver claro en nosotros mismos!»


The concept of God is always coming back to life, as it springs from the ever abiding sensation of God in the heart of humankind. What is this feeling if not an eternal protest of life against reason, an unconquered and invincible instinct to personify? What is the very notion of substance, if not an objectification of the most subjective thing we know, which is will or consciousness? For consciousness, even before it becomes aware of itself as reason, feels itself, touches itself, exists on its own as will, specifically the will not to die. Hence the rhythm we remarked earlier in the history of thought. Positivism brought us an age of reason: in other words, an age of materialism, mechanism, or mortal limitation. And lo! the outcome of this was a return of vitalism, of spiritualism. For what else has pragmatism sought to accomplish besides restoring our faith in the human finality of the universe? What is Bergson (†), for instance, trying to do in his works, especially the one on creative evolution, if not forcibly to restore our personal God and eternal consciousness? Life refuses to surrender.

There's no point in wishing to suppress this mythopoetic or anthropomorphic process, trying to rationalize our thought as though its only purpose were pure cogitation or knowledge, and not living. The very language that holds our thoughts impedes us from thus relinquishing our humanity. As the substance of our thought, our language is a system of metaphors grounded firmly in myths of very human shape. To fashion a purely rational philosophy, we would have to craft it by algebraic formulae, or create a new language for it—an inhuman language, one useless for discussing the necessities of life. Dr. Richard Avenarius (‡), professor of philosophy at Zürich, attempted this in his Critique of Pure Experience, which was calculated to avoid every preconception anyone might have. This vigorous attempt by Avenarius, the captain of the critical positivists, ends in a rigorous and pure skepticism. As the man himself says at the conclusion of the prologue to this book, “It is some time since our infantile confidence of discovering the truth has disappeared. The further we advance, the more we realize the difficulties of this terrain, and the limits of our powers. What is the end of our quest? … We merely wish to achieve clear insight into ourselves!”


---
() Henri-Louis Bergson (1859-1941) was a French philosopher who argued that reality is best grasped by our immediate experiences rather than any abstract reasoning. He did this from a position essentially modern and secular, having left Judaism after discovering Darwinian evolution as a teenager. He published several works, including the famous Creative Evolution (L'Évolution créatrice, pub. 1907). He preferred metaphors to concepts, noting that nobody rational would deduce our ability to swim from any concept derived from the way we walk on land: swimming emerges for conception only after we enter the water. All concepts for him were post hoc reflections of real experience.

() The Swiss philosopher Richard Ludwig Heinrich Avenarius (1843-1896) wanted to describe our experiences in perfectly rational terms, without recourse to metaphors that make up historical language. His tradition was continued by Ernst Mach, and drew ire from Lenin, when Avenarius criticized the materialism of Carl Vogt.