Our being. Unamuno, Life 7.17

For us, to be is to be doing, and doing is a process that requires feeling. It is not enough to think the world; we must feel it to know what we think.


El hombre no se resigna a estar, como conciencia, solo en el Universo, ni a ser un fenómeno objetivo más. Quiere salvar su subjetividad vital o pasional haciendo vivo, personal, animado al Universo todo. Y por eso y para eso ha descubierto a Dios y la sustancia, Dios y sustancia que vuelven siempre en su pensamiento de uno de otro modo disfrazados. Por ser conscientes nos sentimos existir, que es muy otra cosa que sabernos existentes y queremos sentir la existencia de todo lo demás, que cada una de las demás cosas individuales sea también un yo.

El más consecuente, aunque más incongruente y vacilante idealismo, el de Berkeley, que negaba la existencia de la materia, de algo inerte y extenso y pasivo, que sea la causa de nuestras sensaciones y el substracto de los fenómenos externos, no es en el fondo más que un absoluto espiritualismo o dinamismo, la suposición de que toda sensación nos viene, como de causa, de otro espíritu, esto es, de otra conciencia. Y se da su doctrina en cierto modo la mano con las de Schopenhauer y Hartmann. La doctrina de la Voluntad del primero de estos dos y la de lo Inconsciente del otro, están ya en potencia en la doctrina berkeleyana, de que ser es ser percibido. A lo que hay que añadir: y hacer que otro perciba al que es. Y así el viejo adagio de que operari sequitur esse, el obrar se sigue al ser, hay que modificarlo diciendo que ser es obrar y sólo existe lo que obra, lo activo, y en cuanto obra.


Mankind is not resigned to being the only consciousness in the Universe, nor to being just another objective phenomenon like the rest. We want to save our vital & passionate subjectivity by vivifying, personifying, and animating all the Universe. For this reason we have discovered God and substance, two things that return constantly to us under one guise or another. Being conscious means that we feel our existence, which is very different from knowing it intellectually, and we desire to feel the existence of all other things. We want each of them to be another self, an ego like ours.

The most significant idealist position, though it is incoherent and vacillating, is the one taken by Berkeley, who denied the existence of matter. For him, there is nothing inert, extended, and passive that can be taken as the cause of our feelings, or the substrate of external phenomena. The foundation of this conception is an absolutely spiritual or dynamic understanding of the world, which supposes that every feeling reaches us as the effect or imprint of another spirit than our own, i.e. another consciousness. His doctrine has a certain affiliation with those taught by Schopenhauer and Hartmann (†). Schopenhauer's doctrine of Will and Hartmann's doctrine of the Unconscious are both latent in Berkeley's observation, that being is perception. To this we should add that being is also making another perceive one's own existence. And so we must modify the old adage, that function follows being, to say that being is function, and the only thing that exists is something active, something that functions, something that can only be seen or known insofar as it does work.


---
(†) Karl Robert Eduard von Hartmann (1842-1906) posited will & reason as equal partners in expressing the stirring or process by which unconsciousness turns into consciousness, which has desire (will) & teleology (reason). He thought Schopenhauer wrong to make will prior to reason. Originally destined for a military career, bad knees led him to philosophy, where he made a living selling books, refusing professorships.