Begging the question. Unamuno, Life 5.5

Unamuno offers a rational critique of arguments attempting to separate the soul from matter, specifically the human body of flesh and bone that makes our personal thought possible.


Es lo corriente que en los libros de psicología espiritualista, al tratarse de la existencia del alma como sustancia simple y separable del cuerpo, se empiece con una fórmula por este estilo: Hay en mí un principio que piensa, quiere y siente ... Lo cual implica una petición de principio. Porque no es una verdad inmediata, ni mucho menos, el que haya en mí tal principio; la verdad inmediata es que pienso, quiero y siento yo. Y yo, el yo que piensa, quiere y siente, es inmediatamente mi cuerpo vivo con los estados de conciencia que soporta. Es mi cuerpo vivo el que piensa, quiere y siente. ¿Cómo? Como sea.

Y pasan luego a querer fijar la sustancialidad del alma, hipostasiando los estados de conciencia, y empiezan porque esa sustancia tiene que ser simple, es decir, por oponer, al modo del dualismo cartesiano, el pensamiento a la extensión. Y como ha sido nuestro Balmes uno de los espiritualistas que han dado forma más concisa y clara al argumento de la simplicidad del alma, voy a tomarlo de él tal y como lo expone en el cap. II de la Psicología de su Curso de Filosofía Elemental. «El alma humana es simple» dice y añade: «Es simple lo que carece de partes, y el alma no las tiene. Supóngase que hay en ella las partes A, B, C; pregunto: ¿Dónde reside el pensamiento? Si sólo en A, están de más B y C; y, por consiguiente, el sujeto simple A será el alma. Si el pensamiento reside en A, B y C, resalta el pensamiento dividido en partes, lo que es absurdo. ¿Qué serán una percepción, una comparación, un juicio, un raciocinio, distribuídos en tres sujetos?» Más evidente petición de principio no cabe. Empieza por darse como evidente que el todo, como todo, no puede juzgar. Prosigue Balmes: «La unidad de conciencia se opone a la división del alma: cuando pensamos, hay un sujeto que sabe todo lo que piensa, y esto es imposible atribuyéndole partes. Del pensamiento que está en la A, nada sabrán B ni C, y recíprocamente; luego no habrá una conciencia de todo el pensamiento; cada parte tendrá su conciencia especial, y dentro de nosotros habrá tantos seres pensantes cuantas sean las partes». Sigue la petición de principio; supónese, porque sí, sin prueba alguna, que un todo como todo no puede percibir unitariamente. Y luego Balmes pasa a preguntar si esas partes A, B, C son simples o compuestas, y repite al argumento hasta venir a parar a que el sujeto pensante tiene que ser una parte que no sea todo, esto es, simple. El argumento se basa, como se ve, en la unidad de apercepción y de juicio. Y luego trata de refutar el supuesto de apelar a una comunicación de las partes entre sí.

Balmes, y con él los espiritualistas a priori que tratan de racionalizar la fe en la inmortalidad del alma, dejan de lado la única explicación racional: la de que la apercepción y el juicio son una resultante, la de que son las percepciones o las ideas mismas componentes las que se concuerdan. Empiezan por suponer algo fuera y distinto de los estados de conciencia que no es el cuerpo vivo que los soporta, algo que no soy yo, sino que está en mí.


Contemporary books of spiritualizing psychology, when they treat the soul as a simple substance separable from the body, begin with a formula like this: There is in me a principle that thinks, desires, and feels ... This is begging the question, as it is not immediately or even remotely true that such a principle exists within me. The immediate truth is simply that I am thinking, desiring, and feeling. The ego that is myself in this immediate moment, as I think, desire, and feel, is my living body, with all the states of consciousness that it carries. My live body is the thing that thinks, desires, and feels. How so? However it may be.

After asserting the existence of the soul these books go on to fix its substantiality, reifying the states of our consciousness. They begin this process by opposing thought to matter, in the style of Descartes, because they insist on making soul a simple substance, uncompounded and elemental. As our own Balmes () has provided a most concise and clear version of this sort of spiritualizing argument, I shall take it from him and present it here, as set forth in the second chapter on Psychology in his Course of Elementary Philosophy. "The human soul is simple," Balmes says. "A simple thing lacks parts, and the soul has none. Suppose that it did have parts, which we can refer to here as A, B, and C. I have a question: Where in the soul does thought reside? If it lives only in A, then B and C are superfluous. Thus, the simple subject A becomes the soul. If thought resides in A, B, and C, then their partition means that it too is parted, broken up into pieces of itself, which is absurd. Where would we find integrity in a perception, comparison, judgment, or argument distributed among three separate parts?" So blatantly he begs the question! Beginning his argument on the premise that a compounded whole is incapable of rendering judgment. Balmes continues: "The unity of our consciousness opposes any division in the soul. When we think, there is in us one subject who knows all that is thought, and this is impossible if we attribute parts to our faculty for thinking. If we assume partition in the soul, parts B and C will have no idea what is going on in part A, and vice versa. The outcome of such an arrangement would not be any singular consciousness comprehending all our thought. Instead, each part would have its own special consciousness, separate from the others, and we would contain within ourselves as many different thinking individuals as the number of parts in our soul." Still begging the question! We are to suppose, without any proof at all, that no compounded whole is capable of unified or unitary perception. Balmes' next move is to inquire whether parts A, B, and C are simple or compound, and he repeats the argument above, concluding it with the observation that a thinking subject must be a part that does not belong to any larger whole, i.e. that it must be simple. The foundation of his argument, as you can see, is the unity of our perception and judgment. He then goes on to attempt a refutation of the notion that unified expressions might arise from a soul with parts that communicate among themselves.

Like all the committed spiritualizers who attempt to rationalize faith in the soul's immortality without questioning their premises, Balmes leaves out the only rational explanation of the phenomena he discusses: that perception and judgment are acts constitutive of themselves, that our observations and ideas are capable of influencing one another directly, as parts of one whole, without any external mediation. These spiritualizers begin by supposing the existence of something outside and distant from our states of consciousness which is not our living body, the thing that actually supports those states. They want me to become the expression of something that is not myself, of something foreign that occupies me.


---
() Jaime Luciano Balmes y Urpiá (1810-1848) was a Catholic priest from Catalonia, known for his unique approach to philosophy and Catholic apologetics. He saw his own thought as resting upon three pillars: (i) Cartesian consciousness (cogito ergo sum: I think therefore I am); (ii) non-contradiction (a thing cannot be at once X and not-X); and (iii) the intellectual instinct (we know that truth exists, and perceive correspondence between the world and our perception of it). After producing two seminal books, one called Fundamental Philosophy and the other the Course of Elementary Philosophy referenced here by Unamuno, he died of tuberculosis in his hometown of Vic. The argument he uses in the passage quoted is quite similar to one used by ancient Buddhists to demonstrate the ubiquity of mind (is my thought confined to one part of my body? no, as I can lose parts and still think: so, when I am no longer aware of thinking, thought goes on; it must come to me from somewhere beyond myself). Unamuno opposes all these arguments with the observation that thought presents itself to us as the personal expression of a material body that is mortal, that appears to gain and lose its powers of thinking as it comes to life and then dies.