Life: social tragedy or individual dilemma? Unamuno, Life 4.11

Unamuno sees Catholicism maintaining an ancient commitment to communion and community that Protestants lose, in part because they focus too much on rational ethics, which belong properly to individuals (rather than groups) and to this world (rather than any other). He finds minimal room for heroic self-sacrifice in forms of religion which allow themselves to become simply ethical (a matter of finding the right, sensible thing and doing it, with no fuss or tragedy). His Catholics are religious because they must confront the tragedy of life being inherently unsolved and insoluble, and they rise to that challenge sacramentally, ritually—in the context of a living tradition that never achieves a perfectly rational ethic like Kant's categorical imperative. Communion with Christ, on Unamuno's reading, requires a social unity or integrity that defies the ability of any individual among us to capture with reason, or express with any singular ethic separated from all others by shared reason. Justification of the individual, a core tenet of Protestantism (on Unamuno's reading), is not that important for Catholics, who read life as a social tragedy rather than an individual moral dilemma.


No ha sido la preocupación del pecado nunca tan angustiosa entre los católicos, o por lo menos, con tanta aparencialidad de angustia. El sacramento de la confesión ayuda a ello. Y tal vez es que persiste aquí más que entre ellos el fondo de la concepción primitiva judaica y pagana del pecado como de algo material e infeccioso y hereditario, que se cura con el bautismo y la absolución. En Adán pecó toda su descendencia, casi materialmente, y se trasmitió su pecado como una enfermedad material se trasmite. Tenía, pues, razón Renán, cuya educación era católica, al revolverse contra el protestante Amiel, que le acusó de no dar la debida importancia al pecado. Y, en cambio, el protestantismo, absorto en eso de la justificación, tomada en un sentido más ético que otra cosa, aunque con apariencias religiosas, acaba por neutralizar y casi borrar lo escatológico, abandona la simbólica nicena, cae en la anarquía confesional, en puro individualismo religioso y en vaga religiosidad estética, ética o cultural. La que podríamos llamar «allendidad», Jenseitigkeit, se borra poco a poco detrás de la «aquendidad», Diesseitigkeit. Y esto, a pesar del mismo Kant, que quiso salvarla, pero arruinándola.

La vocación terrenal y la confianza pasiva en Dios dan su ramplonería religiosa al luteranismo, que estuvo a punto de naufragar en la edad de la ilustración, de la Aufklärung, y que apenas si el pietismo, imbuyéndole alguna savia religiosa católica, logró galvanizar un poco. Y así resulta muy exacto lo que Oliveira Martins decía en su espléndida Historia da civilasação iberica, lib. 4.º, cap. III; y es que «el catolicismo dió héroes y el protestantismo sociedades sensatas, felices, ricas, libres, en lo que respecta a las instituciones y a la economía externa, pero incapaces de ninguna acción grandiosa, porque la religión comenzaba por despedazar en el corazón del hombre aquello que le hace susceptible de las audacias y de los nobles sacrificios». Coged una Dogmática cualquiera de las producidas por la última disolución protestante, la del ritschleniano Kaftan, por ejemplo, y ved a lo que allí queda reducida la escatología. Y su maestro mismo, Albrecht Ritschl, nos dice: «El problema de la necesidad de la justificación o remisión de los pecados sólo puede derivarse del concepto de la vida eterna como directa relación de fin de aquella acción divina. Pero si se ha de aplicar ese concepto no más que al estado de la vida de ultratumba, queda su contenido fuera de toda experiencia, y no puede fundar conocimiento alguno que tenga carácter científico. No son, por lo tanto, más claras las esperanzas y los anhelos de la más fuerte certeza subjetiva, y no contienen en sí garantía alguna de la integridad de lo que se espera y anhela. Claridad e integridad de la representación ideal son, sin embargo, las condiciones para la comprensión, esto es, para el conocimiento de la conexión necesaria de la cosa en sí y con sus dados presupuestos. Así es que la confesión evangélica de que la justificación por la fe fundamental lleva consigo la certeza de la vida eterna, es inaplicable teológicamente, mientras no se muestre en la experiencia presente posible esa relación de fin» (Rechtfertigung und Versöhnung, III, cap. VII, 52). Todo esto es muy racional, pero ...


Preoccupation with sin has never been as anxious among Catholics as Protestants, at least as far as outward appearances go. The sacrament of confession helps this. Perhaps the Catholics retain a closer hold on the primitive foundation laid by Jews and pagans, who conceived sin as something material, infectious, and hereditary, to be cured with baptism and absolution. In Adam occurred the sin of all his descendants—materially, as it were—and his sin passed down to us as a material, physical illness would. And so Renan, educated by Catholics, was right to revolt against the Protestant Amiel (†), who accused him of failing to give sin its due. And Protestantism, for its part, becoming absorbed in the idea of justification—which it takes in a sense more ethical than religious, though it retains the outward forms of religion—ends up neutering and almost destroying eschatology. Abandoning the shared symbolic discourse of Nicea, it falls into confessional anarchy, reducing religion to a purely individual matter and leaving the community nothing but a vaguely religious affect, ethical or cultural. What we might call the world beyond, the Otherworld of the religious, is erased little by little behind the rising profile of this world, the province of secular moralists. This happens in spite of Kant, who wanted to save the Otherworld, but instead managed only to proclaim its final ruin.

Lutheranism takes its religious vulgarity from being thoroughly devoted to worldly affairs, and from an apathetic confidence in God, soon to be shipwrecked in the age of Enlightenment, the Dawn of Reason whose blistering attack on the tree of religion was scarcely healed by whatever sap the Pietists (‡) managed to scrounge from Catholicism. And so the judgment expressed by Oliveira Martins (*) in his excellent History of Iberian Civilization (book 4, chapter 3) is utterly correct: "Catholicism created heroes, but the product of Protestantism was societies: sensible, happy, wealthy, free in terms of their institutions and external economy, but incapable of any heroic action, for Protestant religion begins by destroying the capacity of the human heart to conceive great deeds and noble sacrifices." Take any of the professions of faith produced by the latest Protestant rebellion, that of Albrecht Ritschl's student Kaftan for example, and see there the pitiful remains of what used to be eschatology. Ritschl himself (⁑), the master of this pupil, addresses us thus: "The need for justification, or remission of sins, can only arise as a problem from the conception of eternal life as a direct experience, an end of the divine action that begins with creation. If the concept of eternal life applies only to the state of life that exists beyond the grave, however, then its content remains outside all our mortal experience, and it cannot serve as a basis for any knowledge of a scientific character. The hopes and desires of the strongest subjective certainty are thus no clearer or brighter than any others, and in themselves they carry no assurance of the integrity of that which they represent to us. Still, comprehension requires us to meet the conditions of clarity and integrity as we represent any ideal to our minds: we must recognize how the thing represented is a necessary expression, proceeding inevitably from grounds we allow a priori. So the evangelical confession that justification by faith brings with itself a certainty of eternal life finds no place in theology, since our present experience provides no information validating the conception of its end present in this confession" (Justification and Atonement 3.7.52). This is all very rational, but ...


---
(†) Joseph Ernest Renan (1823-1892) and Henri-Frédéric Amiel (1821-1881) were contemporaries who read and criticized each other's work. Unamuno refers here to an essay of Renan's translated by Isabel Hapgood (Recollections and Letters of Ernest Renan, published 1892, pp. 262-295), in which he discusses Amiel's posthumously published Journal.

(‡) A Lutheran revivalist movement that began with the ministry of Philipp Jakob Spener (1635-1705), who wanted to foster traditions of personal and communal devotion (notably the study of scripture and public preaching) among Protestants. Kant (1724-1804) was raised as a Pietist, and the movement had a strong influence on the founders of Methodism, including John Wesley (1703-1791).

(*) Joaquim Pedro de Oliveira Martins (1845-1894) was a Portuguese businessman and historian, remembered for his conception of history as narrative rather than science.

(⁑) Albrecht Ritschl (1822-1899) was a professor of theology at Bonn and then Göttingen. He wrote several books, including the one Unamuno quotes here (arguing that faith is irrational, or perhaps better, beyond rational, since it cannot derive from simple facts). Julius Wilhem Martin Kaftan (1848-1926) accepted and continued his tradition, maintaining that effective faith is a personal, individual reconciliation with God, who does not need or seek to redeem humanity writ large.